For a religionist who believes in
the supernatural, miracles, and the soul, the idea that humans can miraculously
create themselves independently of all causality is no big deal. Hell, if you believe
in an “almighty god” that miraculously created the cosmos, accepting that
humans have the god-like ability to create themselves comes easy. This position is
known philosophically as “libertarianism.” Such libertarians maintain that the
special human freedom essential for moral responsibility must be independent of
natural explanation and all natural causes. Contemporary libertarian free will
has, over the last century or so, under the influence of the increasing success
of scientific, natural explanations, become a bit more modest.
An example of this more
restrained libertarianism is C. A. Campbell, who acknowledges the influences
of heredity and environment that prevent any “man” from having a “voice in
determining the raw material of impulses and capacities” and thus casting doubt
on “whether there is any act of will at all of which one can truly say that the
self is sole author, sole determinant.” His solution to this situation it to
reduce the scope of the free will function. Rather than “making ourselves from
scratch,” he argues that we make small, decisive choices that are the basis of
moral responsibility. His free will has been referred to as a “free will of the
gaps,” as it is only when we experience conflict between desire and duty that
we have this “special power” to exert or withhold the moral effort required to restrain
our desire and accomplish our duty. Campbell accepts that science can explain
how desires are shaped, and the causes of much of our character and behavior,
but asserts that science has no causal accounting of the inner act of exerting will power,
which leaves a “gap” for the exercise of “acausal free will.”
As with the problem of the “god
of the gaps,” when free will is placed in the gap of our scientific knowledge,
it becomes vulnerable to the closing of those gaps. In this case, Campbell’s
“gap” closed awfully quickly when neuroscience showed that one’s capacity to
exert will power depends upon subtle but identifiable psychological factors,
including one’s locus of control, one’s sense of self efficacy, and one’s
degree of learned helplessness.
Clearly, we have an introspective
sense of a conscious free will power that causes our acts and choices, but
there is strong evidence that this sense of self-directed unconstrained will is
not at all reliable. Here is not the place to go into great detail regarding this
evidence, but a solid summary of the evidence can be found in The Illusion of Conscious Will (2002) by
Daniel Wegner.
Briefly, there are cases where we
have a strong sense of consciously willing an action when in fact we have
performed no action at all; there are also cases in which one performs an action but
experiences no sense of willing (obvious cases involve the Ouija board and
so-called “facilitated communication”); as well as cases where one has a strong
sense of having freely chosen and willed an act when in fact the choice was
actually under the control or strong influence of external factors. An
interesting example of this is when electrical stimulation of an area of the
brain caused patients to turn their head from side to side. When asked, “What
are you doing?” the patients always gave a reasonable answer such as “I’m
looking for my slippers” or “I heard a noise.” Other experiments show this
tendency we have to create reasons for our behavior after the fact.
One of my favorite social
experiments shows how even trivial, unrecognized factors can influence and lead to
dramatic and powerful effects on our behavior. In 1972, (when public phone
booths were common) one group of experimental subjects found a dime in a phone
booth and other subjects did not. As each subject left the phone booth, one of
the experimenters (the subjects were unaware this was an experiment and that
this person was part of the experiment) walked by and dropped an armful of
papers he was carrying. The subjects who had found a dime nearly invariably
stopped to help the experimenter pick up the papers while most of the subjects
who did not find a dime simply walked on by! Subjects never gave finding a dime
as a reason for why they helped, but the evidence strongly suggests it had a
profound effect. Similar experiments have gone on to show that subtle
situational factors have a much greater effect on our choices and behaviors
than does any “underlying character,” all of which is in line with the
anti-essentialist understanding of buddhism which posits causes and conditions
over any substantialist understanding of “self-nature.”
On the basis of these
experimental results, Wegner proposes an epiphenomenal account of the conscious
experience of willing: the unconscious impulse to act occurs first and the
conscious awareness of willing arises as a by-product of that unconscious
decision, informing us that the willed action is our own. In this way, the
experience of willing serves as useful feedback letting us know that an action
came from “within” and thus was our own, and not the result of any external
causal force (the movement of my fingers on the keyboard come from my own brain
operations and nor from someone manipulating my fingers).
I hope you can see from this that
Wegner is saying that while my fingers moving over the keys of my laptop is my
free act, he denies that my “experience of conscious willing” is evidence of
some special power of free will that is the source of my behavior. The vast
range of experimental evidence covered by Wegner makes an impressive case
against the truth status of our sense of conscious free willing. The
ontological existence of some independent free will would need a much stronger
basis than our incredibly unreliable sense of acting from freely efficacious
willing.
Our experience of freedom signals
to us that the action we have taken is our own action that comes from our own
choices rather than being the product of some external force. If your arm is
lifted by someone else, it is a very different experience than the experience
of freely choosing to move your arm. The movement was initiated nonconsciously,
but it is still your own movement
rather than some external force. This is a naturally evolved useful tool for
distinguishing our own motions from those initiated externally. This
epiphenomenal understanding will have relevance for the later distinguishing of
“action responsibility” from “moral responsibility” in that while we have the
former, there is no real evidence of the latter.
1 comment:
Hello! I am Daniel Strain, Director of the Spiritual Naturalist Society. I was wondering how we might contact one another? I would be interested in discussing some things with you, if you would like to email me at spiritualnaturalistsociety [at] gmail [dot] com. Many thanks :)
Post a Comment